Class-Based Affirmative Action: A Natural for Labor
By Richard
D. Kahlenberg
President Clinton's
initiative on race has come back, time and time again, to the nagging question
of affirmative action, and for good reason.
While most fair-minded Americans are supportive of strong
antidiscrimination laws -- against bias in employment, housing, and education
-- Americans are deeply divided over whether racial preferences are an
appropriate means of remedying past discrimination and fostering integration in
higher education and the workforce. For
most of the quarter century experiment with racial preferences, the labor
movement has been as deeply divided over affirmative action as the rest of the
country. The time has come for a new
compromise on the affirmative action question -- preferences based on class or
socioeconomic status rather than race or gender. This class-based alternative is more
appealing morally, politically, and legally; and because it is rooted in the
bedrock reality of class unfairness, it ought to be especially appealing to the
labor movement.
A DIFFICULT ISSUE
The affirmative action question fascinates, divides, and
tears at Americans because neither side of the debate can be easily
dismissed. On the one hand, liberals are
clearly right to say that the history of discrimination in this country has
left a legacy of racial inequality that needs to be addressed proactively --
beyond simply outlawing future discrimination.
If anyone visits the affluent suburbs in this country, and comes across
African Americans or Latinos, the chances are quite good that they are there
not as residents but as garbage collectors, gardeners, or child care
providers. Such is not a colorblind
society.
On the other hand, conservatives make a powerful case
that we need to be very, very cautious before employing racial preferences when
the long term goal is a colorblind society.
The casualness with which many advocates of affirmative action now
embrace using skin color to decide who should get ahead in society is
astonishing. Some advocates say counting
race in college admissions is no different than the consideration of other
nonacademic factors, such as musical or athletic ability. But these advocates ignore the fundamental
reason racial discrimination is morally repugnant in the first place. As a rule, people should be judged by factors
within their control. An athlete or
violin player can develop her skills through hard work and diligence; skin
color is an accident of birth. The
color-consciousness of today's left is particularly disturbing as the basis for
racial preferences has shifted: where
once preferences were justified as a temporary remedy for past discrimination,
today preferences are normally supported by the idea that diversity is an
overriding and self-justifying goal, and will be forevermore. This vision of unending color-consciousness
is highly unappealing to most Americans.
Finally, both liberals and conservatives are noting with
increasing frequency the fundamental unfairness of class-blind racial
preferences. Since racial affirmative
action counts skin color but ignores economic circumstances, it necessarily
prefers the son of a black doctor over the son of a white garbage collector. With the growth of the black middle class in
recent years, the likelihood that race and class will collide in this manner
has increased dramatically. When
programs promote such patent unfairness, they lose their moral force. These programs begin to look like any other
reflection of interest group politics and political power, and cease to claim
the mantle of promoting genuine equal opportunity.
The vote on Proposition 209, the California Civil Rights
Initiative to ban race and gender preferences, underlines American ambivalence
over affirmative action. Californians
did vote to abolish such preferences in the public sphere, underlining concerns
about the use of race in deciding who will enjoy the American Dream. But the margin was fairly narrow -- 54-46% --
which suggests that many Californians were unwilling to simply go "cold
turkey."
More recently, a New York Times/CBS News poll found that
Americans polled nationally favor affirmative efforts to help disadvantaged
minorities, but they reject the use of racial preferences to achieve racial
diversity. The poll, published in
December 1997, found that 25% of Americans would "do away with"
affirmative action preferences, 24% would "leave them as they are"
and 43% would "change them."
Is it possible to come up with a compromise on this
issue, one that respects the best arguments on both sides of the affirmative
action debate? Two possible compromises
have emerged to "mend" rather than "end" affirmative
action.
TWO POSSIBLE COMPROMISES
The first possibility -- the position embraced by
President Clinton -- is to say yes to affirmative action preferences, but no to
racial quotas. This compromise has been
called the "Bakke straddle," named after Justice Lewis Powell's
opinion in the famous Bakke case from the 1970s. In that Supreme Court decision, four justices
said the University of California at Davis Medical School's system of quotas was
illegal; four justices said the program was legal; and Justice Powell, casting
the deciding vote, tried to split the difference: quotas are illegal, he said, but using race
as "one factor" in admissions is permissible. U.C. Davis could weight the race of minority
candidates in their favor, but it could not set aside a fixed number of seats
for people of color.
At first, the Bakke straddle was highly criticized by
both sides of the affirmative action debate.
In the Bakke case itself, the liberal justices were most critical: what is the difference, they asked, between
setting aside 16 of 100 seats for minority candidates and using "race as
one factor" in admissions with the committee having a pretty good idea of
what kind of racial makeup they would like to end up with at the end of the
day? Nevertheless, the Bakke straddle
has proven a useful rhetorical device, and whenever President Clinton is asked
a question about affirmative action, the first thing out of his mouth is that
he is opposed to quotas.
But fundamentally the Bakke straddle remains a highly
unstable compromise. If the use of skin
color is seen as fundamentally unfair, it matters not whether the use of race
is a small or large factor. Americans
would never tolerate the idea that racial discrimination against people of
color is permissible, so long as race is just "one factor" used
against a candidate. And in California, and elsewhere, when the
issue is posed not as quotas, but as preferences, Americans make clear their
opposition to such practices. The courts
have become increasingly hostile to the Bakke straddle, and in the 1996 Hopwood
v. Texas case, the 5th Circuit ruled that preferences are
just as illegal as quotas. The Supreme
Court declined to take the Hopwood case, but cases involving the University of Michigan and the University of Washington may eventually end up in
the Supreme Court, and there is a good chance that the Bakke straddle will not
survive.
The second compromise to the affirmative action issue is
to provide preferences on the basis of class or socioeconomic status rather
than race or color. The roots of the
argument lie not in Justice Powell's decision in Bakke, but rather in the writings
of Dr. Martin Luther King, Jr.
In his 1964 book, Why We Can't Wait, King entertained the
argument over affirmative action directly.
King wrote (as advocates of affirmative action note) that compensation
was due: "the nation must not only
radically readjust its attitude toward the Negro in the compelling present, but
must incorporate in its planning some compensatory consideration for the
handicaps he has inherited from the past."
At the same time, King had fought too hard and too long for the goal of
colorblindness -- treating people based on the content of their character not
the color of their skin -- to casually embrace racial preferences as the
optimal means for compensation.
Instead of advocating a new Bill of Rights for the Negro
exclusively, King advocated a Bill of Rights for the Disadvantaged. He wrote, "While Negroes form the vast
majority of America's disadvantaged, there are
millions of white poor who would also benefit from such a bill." In advocating a colorblind program for the disadvantaged,
King had two key insights.
First, King saw that a class-based approach would
implicitly compensate the victims of discrimination. Because of past discrimination, blacks were
disproportionately poor, and would disproportionately benefit from any
class-based program. In this way, the
program would implicitly take account of history. But at the same time, King saw that fairness
demanded the inclusion of poor whites.
Discrimination was not the only cause of unequal opportunity, he knew;
deprivation also blocked opportunity.
Inequality of opportunity in this country runs far deeper
than race and gender discrimination.
Sociological studies over the last several decades have demonstrated the
degree to which children born into poor families find the deck stacked against
them. A child born into the top 10% by
income is 27 times as likely as a child born into the bottom 10% to rise as an
adult to earn in the top 10% bracket.
Poor children -- regardless of race -- are more likely to grow up in violent
neighborhoods, attend inferior schools, and are much less likely to reach their
full natural potential. King knew that
racial discrimination was but one element of societal unfairness, and he wrote: "It is a simple matter of justice that America, in dealing creatively with
the task of raising the Negro from backwardness, should also be rescuing a
large stratum of the forgotten white poor."
Secondly, as a matter of politics, King knew that in the
matter of preferential treatment, emphasizing class over race was
imperative. Toward the end of his life,
King was trying to build a multiracial coalition of disadvantaged people
culminating in the Poor People's Campaign of 1968. He was assassinated in Memphis as he was helping
sanitation workers in a multiracial effort for economic justice. King knew that racial preferences could split
that coalition asunder. He wrote:
"It is my opinion that many white workers whose economic condition is not
too far removed from the economic condition of his black brother, will find it
difficult to accept a 'Negro Bill of Rights,' which seeks to give special
consideration to the Negro in the context of unemployment, joblessness, etc.
and does not take into sufficient account their plight (that of the white
worker)."
But if King worried about the divisive effect of a policy
of racial preference, division was seen as a plus for Richard Nixon, who, in
1969, instituted the first major federal affirmative action program. Nixon offered the Philadelphia Plan, an
effort to impose quotas on the construction industry and trade unions in Philadelphia, in part as a way of
dividing King's progressive coalition.
Nixon aide John Ehrlichman recalled that Nixon delighted in the plan's
ability to construct "a political dilemma for the labor union leaders and
civil rights groups...Before long, the AFL-CIO and the NAACP were locked in
combat over one of the passionate issues of the day."
The great civil rights leader Bayard Rustin, addressing
the AFL-CIO in 1969, said the conflict between labor and civil rights groups
over the Philadelphia Plan was "a source of tremendous satisfaction to the
powerful enemies of the labor movement."
The Plan's intent, Rustin said, was to "deliberately throw black
and white workers at each other's throats." Years later, Rustin would write: "Any
preferential approach postulated on racial, ethnic, religious, or sexual lines
will only disrupt a multicultural society and lead to a backlash. However, special treatment can be provided to
those who have been exploited or denied opportunities if solutions are
predicated on class lines, precisely because all religious, ethnic, and racial
groups have a depressed class who would benefit."
WHAT WOULD A SYSTEM OF
CLASS-BASED AFFIRMATIVE ACTION LOOK LIKE?
Using race and gender-based
affirmative action as a model, one can easily envision a system of preferences
in education, entry-level employment, and government contracting based on
economic status. The basic idea is to
define preferences in a way that take into account the economic obstacles that
poor and working class youth face. If a
youth has faced a number of economic disadvantages -- and done fairly well
despite the odds -- the chances are that her long-run potential is greater than
a colleague who has a similar record of accomplishment having faced none of the
same obstacles.
In the college admissions arena, preferences could be
given to students who are disadvantaged by what sociologists say are the three
major determinants of life chances:
parental income, education, and occupation. That is, students from families with low
incomes, whose parents did not attend college, and whose parents work in low
status occupations should be given a break.
Today, Bard College provides a leg up to
students from low-income families by requiring a notarized copy of IRS form
1040 or letters from a social service agency verifying income. Existing federal guidelines are available to
adjust income for family size or even geographic region to reflect the varying
value of a given income. Given the
importance of a parent's educational level to a student's chances of
educational success, Berkeley provides preferences to
students whose parents do not have a four year college degree. And numerous academic studies dating back 80
years have devised sophisticated and consistent ways to rank parental
occupations.
In addition, a university might consider factoring in
such elements as a family's net worth, the quality of secondary education,
neighborhood influences, and family structure.
Net worth provides a longer term picture of a family's economic position
that goes beyond the snapshot provided by annual income. Counting net worth also uncovers one of the
significant differences between blacks and whites in America: even among whites and African Americans of
the same income group, blacks tend to have lower net worths, in part because
they are less likely to have inherited money from their parents. The quality of secondary education can be measured
by objective standards such as median high school test scores or graduation
rates. If a particular student does
quite well even though he attends an underachieving high school, that student
probably has a great deal to offer in the long term. Neighborhood influences can be measured by such
factors as the poverty or unemployment rate in the applicant's census
tract. This factor reflects strong
sociological evidence that it is a disadvantage to be born into a poor family,
but it is doubly disadvantageous to be born into a poor family living in
concentrated poverty. This factor will,
in the aggregate, tend to benefit people of color, who are generally more
likely to live in concentrated poverty than whites. Finally, a school could consider whether the
applicant was raised in a single parent family.
Numerous studies show that even after controlling for income, growing up
without two parents presents an independent obstacle to success.
Many of these factors -- such as income and net worth --
are already known to college admissions officers through financial aid
offices. Parental
education levels is normally supplied as well. And in recent years schools like the University of California and Los Angeles Law School have succeeded in devising
workable class-based affirmative action programs which go beyond the
information normally available to financial aid and admissions officers.
Because large numbers of low income youth are not in a
position to pursue college, similar preferences could be provided in
entry-level employment to students entering the workforce directly from high
school. The federal government currently
provides such hiring preferences to low income workers who build new public
housing. Likewise, federal contractors
could be required to provide entry level opportunities to disadvantaged youth
as a condition for receiving federal funds, much as such contractors are now
required to take account of race in hiring.
Class-based preferences in promotions down the line make less sense in
part because individuals are more responsible for their economic position as
they grow older, and in part because highly skilled jobs are less amenable to
flexibility in hiring.
In government contracting, preferences can be provided to
small firms (irrespective of the owner's race) which agree to employ
individuals from high poverty census tracts.
In May 1996, for example, President Clinton issued an executive order
directing the Commerce Department to provide preferences to government
contractors employing significant numbers of residents from census tracts with
poverty rates of 20% or more. In New York City, Mayor Ed Koch instituted a
similar program in the 1980s based on economic status rather than race or
gender. The program set aside contracts
for small firms that did at least 25% of their business in depressed areas or
employed economically disadvantaged workers as 25% of their workforce.
All these types of affirmative action will
disproportionately benefit people of color, but will do so on the unifying
basis of class rather than the dividing basis of race. (For those seeking more detail, I outline how
class-based affirmative action might work in chapter 5 of The Remedy: Class,
Race, and Affirmative Action.)
It should be emphasized that class-based preferences
should supplement, rather than supplant, strict enforcement of civil rights
laws. Such laws include not only those
aimed at eliminating intentional discrimination (the Civil Rights Act of 1964)
but also those aimed at hiring practices which result in a statistical racial
imbalance and cannot be justified on nonracial grounds (the Civil Rights Act of
1991). These are powerful tools and
should be backed up with increased funding for government enforcement.
PROSPECTS FOR CLASS-BASED
AFFIRMATIVE ACTION
What is the likelihood that a class-based affirmative
action will be put into place? The
chances increase every day. The attacks
on affirmative action have led both liberals and conservatives to begin talking
seriously about class-based alternatives.
Racial preferences are under heavy attack from the most
democratic institution (the ballot initiative) and the least democratic (the
judiciary). Passage of Proposition 209
in California has spawned similar efforts to cut back on
affirmative action in 1998 in Ohio, Colorado, Florida, and Washington. More severe threats come from the
courts. Proponents of affirmative action
dodged a bullet when civil rights groups settled the case of Piscataway v. Taxman, but new cases
are making their way up to the High Court, and new restrictions are likely.
The legal and political attacks have raised the salience
of the class-based alternative as the left begins contingency planning, and the
right searches for something positive to say.
Among conservatives, Jack Kemp argues affirmative action "should be
done on the basis of income and socioeconomic status such as an enterprise zone
instead of just giving a tax break to someone based on color." And Newt Gingrich argues racial preferences
should be replaced with special help for people "who come out of poor
neighborhoods, who come out of poor backgrounds, who go to school in poor
counties." These statements,
underreported by the mainstream press, constitute a not insignificant
development, considering the inattention conservatives have historically given
to issues of class inequality.
Among Democrats, President Clinton has flirted on an off
with class-based affirmative action. In
March 1995, Clinton made headlines by
declaring, that instead of emphasizing racial preferences "I want us to
emphasize need-based programs where we can because they work better and have a
bigger impact and generate broader support." Clinton quickly backed off that
statement after Jesse Jackson threatened to run for president, but in late
1997, Clinton returned to the concept of need-based
preferences. In the Akron, Ohio town hall meeting, Clinton said "the real
issue" is whether a "class-based affirmative opportunity agenda"
should supplement or replace race-based affirmative action. "I think that's the question," he
stressed; "that's the nub of the affirmative action debate." The president continued: "politically
and substantively you'll help more people and build more unity by having an
economic basis for social policy now."
Public support for class-based affirmative action
continues to grow. In the December 1997
New York Times/CBS poll, Americans supported preferences for people from poor
families by 53%-37%. When asked,
"Is it a good idea to select a person from a poor family over one from a
middle-class or rich family if they are equally qualified," Americans
favored the idea by 2:1 (56%-27%).
What is particularly interesting is the attention younger
people have given to the idea of class-based affirmative action. The younger generation is generally more
racially tolerant, and for that reason sees less need for racial preferences in
coming years. During the debate over
affirmative action in California, the Berkeley student newspaper came out in
favor of paying "special attention to economic status" rather than to
race or gender. When students at Berkeley find common cause with Newt
Gingrich, it is time to take note.
A NATURAL FOR LABOR
In particular, it is time for labor to take note. In the debate over race vs. class-based
affirmative action, what Clinton calls the "nub"
of the affirmative action debate, labor has been astonishingly quiet. There can be little question where the
interests and values of labor historically lay:
in multiracial approaches which benefit working class people
generally. Where racial preferences have
spawned division, class-based affirmative action would unite various races, and
remind the ranks of labor who their true friends are.
Big business has turned out to be a great champion of
affirmative action, which in itself should give labor reason for pause. Under the current legal regime, business can
use preferences to achieve racial balance as a way of fending off suits from
people of color, secure in the knowledge that "reverse discrimination"
suits from whites will rarely prevail.
If affirmative action policies are altered, business will be equally
subject to lawsuits for unfair treatment from all sides. Because business does not want that kind of
accountability, it fought an anti-preference initiative in Houston, Texas in
1997, and it put the bulk of the money up to prevent the Supreme Court from
hearing the arguments in the Piscataway affirmative action layoff case.
With the notable exception of the late Albert Shanker,
labor has done very little to support the class-based alternative to racial
preferences. In another era, labor would
surely have been at the forefront:
policies which polarize workers by race, labor knew, always give
management an advantage.
Class-based affirmative action tries to address the
historic wrongs
highlighted by proponents of racial preferences but uses means
not offensive to the majority of Americans who oppose racial preferences. More importantly, class-based preferences are
firmly rooted in an American sense of fairness -- giving a break to those who
need it -- in a way that unites rather than divides. This is a natural for the American labor
movement. It will be a lasting shame if
the Republicans manage to figure all of this out first.